Social dilemmas: conflict between self and others

Example

You write C or D on a piece of paper. If you write C, I give everyone else $1. If you write D, I give you $1.

If everyone else does the same thing, how does this choice affect you?

How does it affect others?

What would you do if this were real? What proportion of others do you think would write C?

How would you feel if you wrote D and everyone else wrote C? What if you wrote C and everyone else wrote D?

What would you like others to do? How could we change the rules to get them to do that?

Pay-offs for cooperating (C) and defecting (D) as a function of the number of others who cooperate.

payoffs

Schelling diagram of grass walking

Motives for doing what others do

Fear of being a sucker.

Reciprocity: desire to punish defection and reward cooperation.

Conformity. Perhaps a good heuristic.

Social norms (Bicchieri): contingent on expectations and behavior of others; costly; not the same as convention.

Yossarian's view of a social dilemma

"Would you like to see our country lose?" Major Major asked.

"We won't lose [answers Yossarian]. We've got more men, more money and more material. There are ten million men in uniform who could replace me. Some people are getting killed and a lot more are making money and having fun. Let somebody else get killed."

"But suppose everybody on our side felt that way."

"Then I'd certainly be a damned fool to feel any other way. Wouldn't I?"

From Catch 22, Joseph Heller

Trust game (Berg, Dickhaut, & McCabe, 1995)

Trust game (Berg, Dickhaut, & McCabe, 1995)

Government as a 2nd order social dilemma

"We must protect our planet. Turn off your computer!" (betty.happy@yandex.com)

Reducing our personal carbon footprint is not enough:

Advantages of second-order social dilemmas (a.k.a. government)

Voting vs. individual acton: Lower cost/benefit ratio for altruism, but higher for self-interested action.

By design, political action is a relatively efficient way to promote the interests of all, and an inefficient way to promote self-interest.

This is more true, the larger the circle of altruistic concern. E.g., future people.

Why don't we?

A utilitarian voter would vote for what is best for all in the long run.

Instead, people vote parochially (for their nation or generation), or for their self-interest. They may misunderstand the nature of political action.

Note that beliefs may be a secondary problem because of belief overkill.

Voting on fair division:
Eichenberger & Oberholzer-Gee (1998)

Dictator game: Dictator selected for better performance on homework. 7 Swiss Francs. Gave 34.6%.

Gangster game: Left 24.1% for other player.

Democracy game: Vote on amounts for other player. Gangsters increased to 42.2%, closer to what they judged to be fair. (Dictators did not increase significantly, but had less distance to go.)

Voting doesn't pay (for self-interest)

The probability of being decisive vote is about 1/N, so expected utility of voting is the expected difference divided by N (the number of voters). In a national election in the U.S., that could be 100,000,000. If you stand to gain $1,000,000 if your candidate wins, the EV of voting is thus one cent.

But this analysis assumes self-interest only. If you count altruism or moralistic reasons, things are different. But, if you count altruism, why limit it?

Howard Margolis on 1/N

We can think of a drunk with a rifle takig pot shots at a section of slatted fence ten feet wide. His shots tend to cluster toward the middle: most of them fall in the range of four to six fee from the ends. Once in a great while a shot might land exactly on the center slat of the fence, five feet from either end. But there is no bulls-eye or other feature of the setup that gives a special salience to the exact midpoint of the fence.

Howard Margolis, continued

Now in addition, ... we will have further scatter from the intrinsic inaccuracy in the rifle. Even if the rifle happens to be pointed at five feet exactly, there will remain a certain scatter in the impact points. ... [This corresponds to the random variation in the vote totals even if each voter were equally likely to vote for each side.] But so long as this additional source of scatter is small compared with the rest of the randomness in the result, as would be the case either for our rifle analogy of for an empirically tenable probability model in the voting context, the second effect must be trivial. ...

Howard Margolis, continued

If we think of the slats that make up the fence as representing the number of voters, then the probability of hitting the middle one, analogous to P(tie) in the election context, will be inversely proportional to the number of slats into which the ten feet of fence is divided. Similarly, in a plausibly realistic calculation P(tie) will vary inversly with 1/N.
For utilitarians, the expected utility of a vote for each person must be multiplied by N, if it affects N people. Thus, the EU of a vote is roughly N/N times average effect of a vote on each person.

Possible biases: voters' illusion

"If people on my side vote, I'll probably vote too. My voting will thus be linked with theirs. Hence, I'd better vote, because if I don't, they won't either."

Quattrone and Tversky (1984):

"Nonconsequential reasoning"
(Shafir & Tversky, 1992)

When subjects in a two-person prisoner's dilemma were told that their partner had defected, 97% of the subjects defected too.

When they were told that their partner had cooperated, 84% still defected.

But when they did not know what their partner had done, only 63% defected.

Morality-as-self-interest (Baron, 1997)

"Suppose you are an ocean fisherman. The kind of fish you catch is declining from over-fishing. There are 1000 fishermen like you who catch it. The decline will slow down if the fishermen fish less. But, of course, you will lose money if you cut back. Nobody knows how much fish you catch. .... If nobody cuts back, then everyone can keep fishing at roughly their current rate for 2 years and then they will have to stop. Every 100 people who cut back to 50% of their current catch will extend this time for about a year. Thus, if 100 people (out of 1000) cut back this much, fishing can continue for 3 years, and if 200 people cut back, it can continue for 4 years. (It is not expected that many more than this will cut back voluntarily.)"

Morality-as-self-interest, continued

Would you cut back? Would cutting back "increase your income from fishing over the next few years?"

29% saw cooperation as helping them financially in the long run, although it clearly did not.

E.g., "If I cut back now, I would not have to face the fear of running out of fish to sell and I could keep staying in business for a longer time and everyone else would also benefit." "Because if we cut back, there will be more fish for 4 years of 3 years so it would be a greater profit."

Parochialism

Parochialism is an in-group bias in which people try to help their group even when the out-group harm exceeds the in-group benefit.

Historical examples are racism and sexism, but these are no longer respectable, so they require subtle experiments to detect.

Nationalism, however, is alive and well. It is as respectable as racism was in 1800.

Nationalism has some justification, but people's attachment to it may go beyond what is justified and thus lead to worse consequences in some cases.

Biases that support parochialism/nationalism

Parochialism: basic demonstration

In-group cooperation increases when out-group is hurt (Bornstein and Ben-Youssef, 1994), even with arbitrary groups.

Average rate of contribution was 55%. Vs. 27% in control conditions, where the contribution did not affect the other group.

Self-interest illusion (Baron, 2001)

One determinant of the parochialism effect could be that the self-interest illusion is greater when an in-group is in competition with an out-group.

"My cooperation helps people who are X. I am X. Therefore it helps me." This kind of reasoning is easier to engage in when X is a salient property of a particular group than when it is "human."

Baron, J. (2001). Confusion of group-interest and self-interest in parochial cooperation on behalf of a group. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 45, 283-296.

Parochialism and self-interest: Results

Questions:

Those subjects who showed a greater parochialism effect for contributing showed a greater self-interest illusion when the gain for their group was a loss for the other group.

No illusion (self benefit) in a situation that is purely competitive (0 for own group, -4 for other group).

Debiasing (prescriptive, but also descriptive)

Asking people to do the calculations reduces the parochialism effect:

Shows causal effect from illusion to parochialism. (Reverse may happen too.)

A Time to Join: YOUR VOICE COUNTS!

Sometimes you may think that the voice of an individual doesn't count for much. "What does it matter if I join or not?"

While your membership in the Guild is confidential, management is very aware of the total number of members, so every member counts.

A union with more members can do more. It's as simple as that. ...

There's more protection for our jobs, our salaries, and our benefits.

Check out what the Guild won-including 9% wage increases-what it lost, and what it protected you from when the current contract was negotiated.

Another way to debias: approval voting

Group A is the people who live in your country.
Group B is the people who live in another country of the same size.
Both groups vote. Each nation has 10,000,000 voters.

ProposalIncome for group A Income for group B
1 increase by 10% increase by 2%
2 increase by 0% increase by 12%
3 increase by 6% increase by 8%

Which proposal[(s)] would you vote for [approve]?
1    2    3    1 & 2    1 & 3    2 & 3   

The practical philosophy of political participation

Three levels:

Political action in favor of a group often hurts both the actor and humanity.

If people did the arithmetic, self-interest might conspire with utilitarianism to keep parochial voters at home and let the utilitarians run the world.

Morality and voting, item types [dut8]

World vs. U.S.

Jim thinks that the main issue in the election is a tax on carbon fuels in the U.S. Jim thinks that the tax would be bad for the U.S. because of its effects on the economy, but would be good for the world on the whole because it would reduce the harm caused by global warming, harm that would fall mostly on other countries.

Self vs. (slightly) world and U.S.

Betty thinks that the main issue in the election is a tax on carbon fuels in the U.S. Betty thinks that the bad effects of the tax on the world and U.S. economy would slightly outweigh its long-term benefits in reducing global warming, but it would be good for her because she in the solar energy business.

Why might people vote self?

Belief that politics is like a market. Some evidence for this from earlier studies.

Think that voting IS justified by self-interest (and do not see it as promoting morality).

Think that defense of self-interest is moral: norm of self-interest (Ratner and Miller, 2001).

Conclusion

Both self-interest voting and parochial voting may share a similar heuristic or norm, the idea of responsibility for one's own defense. (The "culture of honor" in all of us?)

Like other heuristics, this one may extend to a situation where it is inappropriate. In this case it is not totally useless, but almost.

(It may be more appropriate in protests designed to win the sympathy of others.)

Can we change the norms about when different kinds of action are effective and appropriate? Can people understand the efficiency arguments?

Summary of section

Social dilemmas are real.

Impediments are perceived unfairness and "do no harm".

Second-order social dilemmas can help: low costs.

Impediments here to utilitarian solution: parochialism, self-interest.

These are like naive theories. More understanding of the nature of citizenship might help. (So might approval voting.)