working papers
No. 20. "Of Interest and the Relative Autonomy of Symbolic Power,"
Pierre Bourdieu, trans. L.J.D. Wacquant with M. Lawson, 1988. Most of the questions and objections which have been put to me reveal
a high degree of misapprehension, which can go as far as total
incomprehension. Some of the reasons for this are to be found on the
consumption side, others on the side of production. I shall begin with
the latter. I have said often enough that any cultural producer is
situated in a certain space of production and that, whether he wants it
or not, his productions always owe something to his position in this
space. I have relentlessly tried to protect myself, through a constant
effort of self-analysis, from this effect of the field. But one can be
negatively "influenced," influenced a contrario, if I may say, and
bear the marks of what one fights against. Thus certain features of my
work can no doubt be explained by the desire to "twist the stick in the
other direction," to react against the dominant vision in the
intellectual field, to break, in a somewhat provocative manner, with the
professional ideology of intellectuals. This is the case for instance
with the use I make of the notion of interest, which can call forth the
accusation of economism against a work which, from the very beginning (I
can refer here to my anthropological studies), was conceived in
opposition to economism. The notion of interest--I always speak of
specific interest--was conceived as an instrument of rupture intended to
bring the materialist mode of questioning to bear on realms from which it
was absent and [to bear] on the sphere of cultural production in
particular. It is the means of a deliberate (and provisional)
reductionism which is which is used to take down the claims of the
prophets of the universal, to question the ideology of the
freischwebende Intelligenz [free-floating intellectual]. On this
score, I feel very close to Max Weber who utilized the economic model to
extend materialist critique into the realm of religion and to uncover the
specific interests of the great protagonists of the religious game,
priests, prophets, sorcerers, in the competition which opposes them to
one another. This rupture is more necessary and more difficult in the
sphere of culture than in any other, because we are all both judge and
judged. Culture is our specific capital and, even in the most radical
probing, we tend to forget the true foundation of our specific power, of
the particular form of domination we exercise. This is why it seemed to
me essential to recall that the thinkers of the universal have an
interest in universality (which, incidentally, implies no condemnation
whatsoever). But there are grounds for misunderstanding that stand on the side of
consumption: my critics rely most often on only one book,
Distinction, which they read in a "theoretical" or theoreticist
vein (an inclination reinforced by the fact that a number of concrete
analyses are less "telling" to a foreign reader) and ignore the empirical
work published by myself or others in Actes de la recherche en
sciences sociales (not to mention the ethnographic works which are at
the origin of most of my concepts); they criticize out of their context
of use open concepts designed to guide empirical work; they
criticize not my analyses, but an already simplified, if not maimed,
representation of my analyses. This is because they invariably apply to
them the very modes of thought, and especially distinctions, alternatives
and oppositions, which my analyses are aimed at destroying and
overcoming. I think here of all the antinomies that the notion of habitus
aims at eliminating: finalism/mechanism, explanation by
reasons/explanation by causes, conscious/unconscious, rational and
strategic calculation/mechanical submission to mechanical constraints,
etc. In so doing, one can choose either to reduce my analyses to one of
the positions they seek to transcend, or, as with Elster, to act as if I
simultaneously or successively retained both of these
contradictory positions. These are so many ways of ignoring what seems to
me to be the anthropological foundation of a theory of action, or of
practice, and which is condensed in the notion of habitus: the relation
which obtains between habitus and the field to which it is objectively
adjusted (because it was constituted in regard to the specific necessity
which inhabits it) is a sort of ontological complicity, a subconscious
and prereflexive fit. This complicity manifests itself in what we call
the sense of the game or "feel" for the game (or sens pratique,
practical sense), an intentionality without intention which functions as
the principle of strategies devoid of strategic design, without rational
computation and without the conscious positing of ends. (By way of aside,
habitus is one principle of production of practices among others and,
although it is undoubtedly more frequently at play than any other--"We
are empirical," said Leibniz, "in three quarters of our actions"--one
cannot rule out that it may be superseded, under certain
circumstances--certainly in situations of crisis which disrupt the
immediate adjustment of habitus to field--by other principles, such as
rational and conscious computation. This being granted, even if its
theoretical possibility is universally allocated, the propensity or the
ability to have recourse to a rational principle of production of
practices has its own social and economic conditions of possibility: the
paradox, indeed, is that those who want to admit no principle of
production of practices, and of economic practices specifically, other
than rational consciousness, fail to take into account the economic
preconditions for the development and the implementation of economic
rationality.) To order a copy, please write to Pierre Bourdieu
at the College de France, 54 Blvd. Raspail, 75270 Paris Cedex 06,
France.